89 pages
English

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris

The interpretation of cognitive feelings [Elektronische Ressource] / vorgelegt von Christian Unkelbach

Découvre YouScribe en t'inscrivant gratuitement

Je m'inscris
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus
89 pages
English
Obtenez un accès à la bibliothèque pour le consulter en ligne
En savoir plus

Description

The Interpretation of Cognitive Feelings Dissertation zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Dr. phil. der Fakultät für Verhaltens- und Empirische Kulturwissenschaften der Ruprecht-Karls-Universität zu Heidelberg vorgelegt von Christian Unkelbach aus Bretten Heidelberg, November 2004 Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Klaus Fiedler (Betreuer) Prof. Dr. Herbert Bless ii Acknowledgements The present work was made possible by the help and support of many friends and colleagues, and I wish to express my sincere gratefulness: To my research assistants, Liesa Büche, Marina Kühne, Viola Schreiber, Martin Stegmüller, Martina Wilke and especially, Myriam Bayer, who provided feedback throughout the whole process, conducted the experiments and spotted the largest holes in my reasoning. To Peter Freytag, who meticulously read, corrected and improved an earlier draft of this thesis. To Arie Kruglanski, who sparked the initial idea for the second part of the present thesis. To Herbert Bless, who was my first contact to “the message within”. To Henning Plessner, who always beat me in our tennis matches, but in exchange, also gave me most valuable insights. To all the rest of the Crispies; for many fun lunches, coffee table discussions and shared experiences.

Sujets

Informations

Publié par
Publié le 01 janvier 2005
Nombre de lectures 8
Langue English

Extrait

The Interpretation of Cognitive Feelings
Dissertation
der Fakultät für Verhaltens- und Empirische Kulturwissenschaften
der Ruprecht-Karls-Universität zu Heidelberg
zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades eines Dr. phil.
Prof. Dr. Herbert Bless
Prof. Dr. Klaus Fiedler (Betreuer)
Gutachter:
Heidelberg, November 2004
aus Bretten
vorgelegt von
Christian Unkelbach
ii
Acknowledgements 
The present work was made possible by the help and support of many friends and
colleagues, and I wish to express my sincere gratefulness:
To my research assistants, Liesa Büche, Marina Kühne, Viola Schreiber, Martin
Stegmüller, Martina Wilke and especially, Myriam Bayer, who provided feedback throughout
the whole process, conducted the experiments and spotted the largest holes in my reasoning.
To Peter Freytag, who meticulously read, corrected and improved an earlier draft of
this thesis.
thesis.
To Arie Kruglanski, who sparked the initial idea for the second part of the present
To Herbert Bless, who was my first contact to the message within.
To Henning Plessner, who always beat me in our tennis matches, but in exchange, also
gave me most valuable insights.
To all the rest of the Crispies; for many fun lunches, coffee table discussions and
shared experiences.
To my advisor, Klaus Fiedler, who for over the last 3 years has been providing
guidance by stimulating discussions, by giving me the chance to present my work at many
conferences, and by being a grindstone to sharpen hypotheses and theories. Most importantly,
he provided the freedom to develop and sometimes to discard my own ideas. Thanks, Klaus!
The research was supported financially by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft
(DFG) grant Fi 294/21, awarded to Klaus Fiedler, and the Deusch-Israelische
Projektkooperation (DIP) grant D4.2.
INTRODUCTION
iii
Table of Contents
2
STRUCTURING THE BACKGROUND: ASSUMPTIONS ABOUT COGNITIVE FEELINGS 3
TWO CLASSIC PARADIGMS FOR INVESTIGATING COGNITIVE FEELINGS EXPERIENCING,ATTRIBUTING AND INTERPRETING COGNITIVE FEELINGS EXPERIENCING COGNITIVE FEELINGSATTRIBUTING COGNITIVE FEELINGSINTERPRETING COGNITIVE FEELINGS
PART I – EXPLICITLY PROVIDED INTERPRETATIONS
THE GENERAL PARADIGM OFPARTI
EXPERIMENT 1
METHOD RESULTS DISCUSSION 
EXPERIMENT 2
METHOD RESULTS DISCUSSION 
SUMMARY OF EXPERIMENT 1 AND 2
PART II: INTERPRETATIONS LEARNED VIA ECOLOGICAL FEEDBACK
THEGENERALPARADIGM OFPARTII
EXPERIMENT 3
METHOD RESULTS MENTALROTATIONTASKRECOGNITION TESTRESPONSE LATENCIESRECOGNITION TESTSDT-ANALYSISDISCUSSION 
5 6 677
10
12 
14
16 18 22 
24
25 26 29 
30
32
34 
38
38 42 42444549 
REFERENCES
SUMMARY
GENERAL DISCUSSION
84
CONCLUSION
ASINGLE DIMENSION? IS THE DISTINCTION OF ATTRIBUTION AND INTERPRETATION NECESSARY? UNCONSCIOUS VS.CONSCIOUSPROCESSESLATENCY AS AN INDEX FOR FLUENCYTHE POSSIBLE INHERENT MEANING OF COGNITIVE FEELINGSFORTHCOMING RESEARCH QUESTIONS
626365676970
61
74
72
iv
METHOD RESULTS MENTALROTATIONTASKRECOGNITION TEST-RESPONSE LATENCIESRECOGNITION TEST-SDT-ANALYSISDISCUSSION 
EXPERIMENT 4
52 53 53555659 
51
 
       The Interpretation of Cognitive Feelings
2
Introduction 
We are better prepared to study the content of thought than the experience of thinking. (Clore, 1992; p. 133)
Imagine you were asked to judge the difficulty of a mathematical problem, for
example, the equation 2 + 2 = x. Your immediate reaction might be that this is a very easy
task, probably not even worth the label problem. But on what evidence do you base your
judgment? A justification why this is considered to be an easy task is not complicated: The
mathematical equation consists only of two single digit natural numbers on which the
operation of summation is performed to reach the conclusion that x = 4. This, however, may
not be the reason why you came up with the judgment that this is an easy task. Rather, you
might have used the experience that it is easy to solve the equation, that you instantly knew
the solution. This experience-based route to judgments, decision making and inferences will
be the theme of the present dissertation. It is about the experience of thinking rather than
about the content of thought.
The analytic approach to judgments, decisions and inferences (here, two single digits
involving only summation) has been the dominant model in cognition research for quite some
time, explicitly or implicitly relying on a computer metaphor. One constraint in this tradition
has been that the computer metaphor does not account for the role of affect in judgments (e.g.,
Mellers, Schwartz, & Ritov. 1999). Human beings are not cold information processing units;
emotions, moods, and feelings have a profound influence. Yet, the computer metaphor can
incorporate such affective states by assuming that they enter judgments as information (e.g.,
Schwarz & Clore, 1983; Zajonc, 1980), by assuming that they have a systematic influence on
what information is considered (Bower, 1981; Forgas, 1995), or by assuming that they have a
systematic influence on how information is integrated (Fiedler, 2000; Forgas, 2000).
Besides this obvious constraint, there is another conceptual shortcoming in the
computer metaphor. A computer has no monitoring system for its processes. For instance, a
computer will work through implemented algorithms without realizing a difference between a
simple and a complex operation. It will solve the most complex iterations as well as the
simple task of 2 + 2 = x. A computer cannot use the information how long a calculation takes,
how fast something is accessed on its hard drive, or how long it takes to download
information from a distant source on the internet. Human beings do. The simple task of
judging the difficulty of 2 + 2 = x should serve as an illustration; as said, you probably did not
think about the quality of the problem analytically. Instead, you used the experience resulting
3
from your own cognitive processes. Following the terminology of Clore et al. (2001), such
experiences will be calledcognitive feelingsrationale is that the term feeling. The underlying
is a generic designation for all kinds of internal signals that provide consciously available
feedback from non-conscious affective, bodily, or cognitive processes (Clore et al., 2001, p.
30).
The impact of such cognitive feelings on judgments is for example demonstrated by
Tversky and Kahnemans well-known availability heuristic (Tversky & Kahneman, 1973).
They stated that frequency or probability estimates are based on the ease with which instances
of the event come to mind. For example, if asked to judge the frequency of words starting
with the letter r compared to words with r as the third letter, participants largely
overestimate the first frequency and underestimate the latter (Tversky & Kahneman 1973,
Exp. 3). This is supposedly the case because participants use their subjective experience, their
feeling, that it is easier to come up with words starting with r compared to words with r as
the third letter. Words starting with an r are more available. But what is the underlying
process? The use of the subjective experience of ease in judgments of easiness or difficulty is
reasonable (e.g., in judging the difficulty of 2 +2 x), but why does ease influence frequency =
estimates? There is a silent assumption of an inferential process of the kind that if instances
come easy to mind, they must be frequent. The ease is interpreted in terms of frequency. So,
within the area of research on the experience of thinking, the interpretation of cognitive
feelings will be the main subject of the present thesis.
However, before a model for this interpretation process is presented, a discussion of
the underlying assumptions, a distinction of cognitive and affective feelings and a general
stake out of the presented research seems is called for.
Structuring the background: Assumptions about cognitive feelings
The influence of feelings on judgments in general has been studied mostly in the area
of affective feelings, and there, mostly on a positive  negative valence dimension. The
equivalent in the domain of cognitive feelings is an easy  difficult or a fluent  non-fluent
dimension. Although there are a number of cognitive feelings like revelation (Watkins &
Peynircioglu, 1990), surprise (Reisenzein, 2000; Whittlesea & Williams, 2001), tip-of-the-
tongue (Hart, 1965; for a review, see Schwartz, 2002), they are all derivable from this
dimension. For example, the revelation effect (Bornstein & Neely, 2001; Bernstein,
Whittlesea, & Loftus, 2002) is easy to describe as the experienced difficulty of a cognitive
4
process followed by sudden unexpected ease, which is termed revelation. The following
discussion will therefore concern the ease or fluency of cognitive processes.
Subjective experiences of fluency or ease can result from conceptual processes (e.g.
memory retrieval, information integration, memory storage) or perceptual processes, but the
distinction is blurred. For instance, on a biological level, the first integration of information
takes place on a sub-retinal level. From a definitional point, it is difficult to tell where a
perceptual process ends and a conceptual process starts. As an illustration, it is a daily life
phenomenon that people are able to react when they hear their own name, even if they listen
intensively to something else, for example, when they are engaged in a conversation on a
cocktail party (Cherry, 1953). This phenomenon is hard to explain if a sharp distinction of
conceptual and perceptual, bottom-up and top-down processes, is assumed. And logically, it is
difficult to construe conceptual processes that are devoid of perception and vice versa.
Therefore, conceptual and perceptual processes will be treated as interchangeable. On an
operational level, fluency and ease will be indexed by the speed of responses. It is hard to test
the functional similarity of speed and fluency, but it makes sense intuitively (Reber, Wurtz, &
Zimmermann, 2004): Any process that is fluent or easy should be faster than a non-fluent or
difficult process, be it conceptual or perceptual.
Furthermore, the assumption is made that judgments are based on available
information at the time of judgment (Fiedler, 2000); thus, judgments and decisions based on
existing or preformed opinions are not in the focus of the following. To relate again to the
example from the beginning: If you already have an opinion available whether 2 + 2 = x is
easy, you need not use your experience that it is easy to solve the equation; you can just use
your existing opinion. A similar assumption is found in research on the influence of affect in
judgments and decisions. If opinions and judgments already exist, there is less room for
systematic influences of affective feelings (Forgas, 1995).
Yet, if the judgment is constructed, feelings might influence what information is used,
how it is used or feelings might enter the judgments as direct input. For example, Schwarz
and Clore (1983) showed that people use their mood as input for judgments of how satisfied
they are with their lives. This offers the analogy for the impact of cognitive feelings on
judgments: If an object evokes positive affect, the evaluation of this object will be positive. In
general, evaluative judgments depend on evaluative information, and affective feelings offer a
direct source of such evaluative information. The same is true for the presented math
problem; the cognitive feeling of ease offers a direct source of information for a judgment
about the easiness of a task: Judgments of ease depend on, well, easiness information.
  • Univers Univers
  • Ebooks Ebooks
  • Livres audio Livres audio
  • Presse Presse
  • Podcasts Podcasts
  • BD BD
  • Documents Documents
Alternate Text